PART 1:
A
Reintroduction to Thinking about Politics
Of
all forms of mental activity, the most difficult to induce even in
the minds of the young, who may be presumed not to have lost their
flexibility, is the art of handling the same bundle of data as
before, but placing them in a new system of relations with one
another by giving them a different framework.
Herbert
Butterfield, The Origins of Modem Science
Chapter
1: The American Political Scene: A Blooming, Buzzing Confusion
Chapter
Objectives
By
the time you have finished reading this chapter you should
understand:
1.
Why it is impossible to "introduce" a college student to
American govemment.
2.
Several reasons why government and politics are difficult subjects.
3.
Why we must try to avoid both undersimplifying and oversimplifying
when thinking about politics.
4.
What is meant by a "paradigm" and why the U.S.
Constitution is an example of one.
5.
Some advantages of testing our ideas to see whether they are
compatible with one another.
6.
Several reasons why the Constitution is not an adequate paradigm
upon which to base a study of modem government.
Key Terms
conceptual
acuity
paradigm
inference
simplification
We
have seen that scientific and technological discoveries have
considerable effects on the development of society. It follows that
societies in which scientific and technological discovery is
particularly frequent must be societies in which predictions of their
future condition is particularly hazardous.*
AN
INTRODUCTION
Western
political philosophy goes back at least to the ancient Greeks.
Several centuries B.C., people like Thucydides, Plato, and Aristotle
were trying to think systematically about politics. Their ideas are
still worth examining. If you continue to study government, you
certainly should and probably will read things by the Greek philoso-
phers and their distinguished successors: Thomas Aquinas,
Machiavelli, Thomas Hobbes, John Locke, Jean-Jacques Rousseau, Edmund
Burke, John Stuart Mill, Friedrich Nietzsche, Karl Marx, and many
others. These people had many useful ideas, and this textbook
naturally has been greatly influenced by them. But if the present
work merely expressed old ideas, it would only be an "introduction"
to thinking about politics. it is also a reintroduction. Some of the
approaches suggested here have not been tried before. We speak of a
reintroduction also because few students will find thinking about
politics an entirely new experience. It is impossible to "intro-
duce" people to something with which they are already somewhat
acquainted.
What Makes
Politics Complex?
Politics
can be a difficult study for several reasons. Societies are very
complex. The number of possible interactions among four billion
individuals is incredibly large.
Language.
Language, another complicating factor, is part of the basic stuff of
politics. Campaign oratory, legislative debates and hearings,
communications between bureaucrats, opinions handed down by
courts--all are expressed in words. But let us try to answer the
simple question, What is the opposite of "go"? There are at
least two different answers: "come" and "stop."
But these do not mean the same thing and could themselves be
considered opposites. "Go" therefore must have at least two
different meanings, one of which is the opposite of "come,"
and the other the opposite of "stop." And this is not
unusual! Commonly used political words such as democracy, liberty,
rights, segregation, and aggression often have More than one meaning
or referent; they express more than one concept. We must consider
context in determining what people mean when using words like these.
Students
of politics must therefore try to improve their conceptual acuity,
their ability to see different concepts expressed by a single term.
(When we find this practice a nuisance in others, we ungenerously
call it "hairsplitting.") Sensitivity to language is a must
for those who would think about politics and make sense. "The
meaning doesn't matter if it's only idle chatter." [Footnote
1] If
your instructor has not asked you to do so as a part of your course,
you would do well to get and carefully read a book such as S. 1.
Hayakawa's Language in Thought and Action, Stuart Chase's The Tyranny
of Words, or-for real gluttons for intellectual punishment-Alfred
Korzybski's Science and Sanity.
The
Invisibility of Government. Another complication for students of
politics is govemment's invisibility. As Woodrow Wilson once said,
"No man has ever seen a government. I live in the midst of the
government of the United States, but I never saw the government of
the United States." [Footnote
2] All
that we can see are specific people, buildings, documents. We can see
the president. But the president is not the government. We can see
the Capitol Building, but that building is not the government. We can
see the Constitution, but the Constitution is not the government.
"Government" is a high level abstraction alluding to all of
these things and much more. Its invisibility places us in the same
position as physical scientists studying such unobservable things as
the internal structure of atoms. We must look at what we can see, add
to personal observations the credible reports of others, and put
together an inferential picture of government, just as physicists and
chemists put together inferential models of atomic structure.
Inferences
are conclusions about what cannot be observed based upon what can be.
In drawing inferences, good logic is all important. We do not want to
imitate the six blind men who tried to identify an elephant by
experiencing it in different separate parts. [Footnote
3] We
cannot rest our notions of government or politics upon our experience
of their segments. And if we are to think realistically and
creatively, we must be willing to push our logic to its limits, to
follow ideas wherever they lead.
Remember
that all political discourse is a mixture of sense and nonsense, and
that the two are often integrally related. This is true in the works
of Plato, Alexander Hamilton, Karl Marx, in your own ideas and those
in this textbook. Your job is to try to figure out which is the sense
and which is the nonsense and to avoid the twin pitfalls in
uncritical thinking: accepting blindly and rejecting too quickly.
HOW WE CAN
INFORM OURSELVES
To
be well-informed about American politics, we must read newspapers and
magazines, listen to radio and television, and observe what people
immediately around us are doing and saying. But if we cannot process
them into a composite picture, our efforts to follow current events
will only confuse us. Before discussing strategies for clarifying our
vision, let us look at today's world without benefit of systematic
processing.
An
Unsystematic Survey of the World
In
Georgia no one can be licensed to work as a commercial photographer
unless he can "pass with flying colors a Wasserman test for
syphilis." [Footnote
4] Eighteen
years after the much-applauded Supreme Court decision striking down
racially discriminatory treatment of students by the public schools,
an amendment is offered to the Constitution:
This
Constitution shall not be construed to require that pupils be
assigned or transported to public schools on the basis of their race,
color, religion, or national origin.
The
proposal draws screams of anguish from civil rights groups.
"Fly
now, pay later!" proclaim the travel brochures. Airlines
advertise the joys and comforts of their particular planes, meals,
and stewardesses. Russell Baker, viewing the same panorama, acidly
notes that we "sit strapped in metal containers eating
unspeakable messes while being shot through the air at 500 miles per
hour." [Footnote
5] To
end a strike by Newark, New Jersey, firemen, "state urban aid
funds originally authorized for helping the poor, were diverted to
salary increases." Footnote
6
An
expert predicts that the price of football helmets could increase
from $50 to $300 if present trends in liability insurance costs
continue. [Footnote
7] The
National Association of Parliamentarians decides that
parliamentarians must use the word "chairman" rather than
"chairperson," noting long usage of the expressions "madam
chairman" and "mister chairman." A tax based on the
number of times a person engages in sexual intercourse is
proposed. Footnote
8
Snow
high in acid content falls on North America and Europe. Experts
suggest a connection with increased burning of coal. [Footnote
9] Health
authorities in a small Pennsylvania town provoke public outcries by
efforts to inspect the kitchens of people making things for
charitable baked goods sales. Footnote
10
William
Howard Taft, the only man to serve both as president and as chief
justice of the Supreme Court, observes that "I have heard of the
man who went into office with a majority and left with
unanimity." [Footnote
11] President
Richard Nixon abdicates, but not with unanimous approval. Some
Americans would have him stay, for one reason or another. Others will
not be satisfied unless he immolates himself on prime time
television. Of 120 families offered $500 each to give up watching TV
for a month, 93 turn the offer down.Footnote
12
English
Prime Minister Edward Heath, who went through college on a pipe organ
scholarship, says he had no stomach for the nastiness of a musical
career. "I did not want anything to do with unpleasantness, so I
went into politics. [Footnote
13] Two
coeds at MIT publish an article "in which they rated the sexual
performance of 36 male students by name, awarding each from four
stars to none. . . . The women said they based the ratings on
personal experience." Footnote
14
Dr.
Henry Kissinger comments on right wing extremists opposing his
arrangements for President Nixon to visit Red China: "They sound
very much like leftwing extremists, only their vocabulary is not as
good." [Footnote
15] Inflation
continues. Unemployment goes down, and then goes up again. New
scandals regarding bribes paid by multinational corporations to
government officials come to light. Taxes now constitute the largest
single item in the average individual's cost of living--more than
food, shelter, or clothing--and are also increasing faster than the
other items that make up the cost of living. Warning: apricot pits
may be dangerous to your health. Pope reaffirms opposition to birth
control and abortion. Inflation continues. U.S. attacked in the U.N.
Warning: children's pajamas fireproofed by requirement of federal law
may be dangerous to health. . . . Plane crashes. . . . Seat belt use
in automobiles decreases. . . . Record small voter turnout. Congress
continues energy debate . . .
A System
for Making Sense of the World: Three Strategies
To
avoid being swamped by the facts which are available for our
attention, we must adopt intellectual strategies. We will consider
three useful strategies here: (1) avoiding undersimplification; (2)
being self-conscious about paradigms; and (3) striving for
consistency in thinking.
Avoiding
Undersimplification. That people are rarely accused of
undersimplifying may suggest something about our society. Everybody
knows that oversimplifying is bad, but fewer people today seem aware
of the opposite danger. Our world offers an infinite variety of
events. Literally, we can never step into the same river twice.
Different molecules of water are present at different times. The
currents, temperatures, lighting, pollution levels, etc., are never
exactly the same. As long as we focus on this variety with no
theoretical processing, conscious or unconscious, we can never
understand our environment. Without processing, our world is a
blooming, buzzing confusion.
An
"unprocessed" world may resemble that perceived by young
babies. To babies, almost all experiences are equally alien and
equally interesting. At first, a baby may perceive no patterns, no
repetitions, no regularities in the world around it. What parents see
as repetitions of the same event, such as changing a diaper, may not
seem repetitive to the baby. The words said, the lighting, the order
in which cleaning operations are undertaken, may seem to be
completely unique occurrences.
We
do not have a basis for predicting the future until we can perceive
regularities. Until we see "repetitions," we can have no
language. Language itself appears rooted in classified experiences,
different events lumped into the same "class" or category.
To classify, we abstract, we concentrate on similarities and ignore
many differences. A simple word like "election," for
example, can refer to extremely diverse events: the public
rubber-stamping of official candidates in the U.S.S.R., the
characteristic two party battles in U.S. presidential politics, the
multiringed circuses in European countries with five or more major
political parties.
Abstraction,
classification, and language itself are thus forms of simplification.
They are tools with which we avoid undersimplifying. They help make
our complex physical and social environments intellectually
manageable. By putting apples into the same category as the moon,
Newton was able to formulate the modern laws of motion and gravity.
Similar simplifications are equally necessary for thinking about the
equally complicated world of politics.
Of
course, the more commonly feared problem of oversimplification is
itself all too real. "Earth, air, fire, and water" proved
to be an oversimplification, and modern chemistry did not take off
until the more complex classification of Mendelyeev's periodic table
was put forward. As Aristotle indicated over 2000 years ago,
"goodness is the quality that hits the mean. . . . [Virtue is] a
mean condition as lying between two forms of badness, one being
excess and the other deficiency." [Footnote
16] We
must seek neither the greatest possible simplification, nor the
least. We must aim for that degree of simplification most conducive
to profitable thinking about the problems at hand.
Paradigms.
A second strategy for thinking about politics is to develop
self-consciousness about our use of paradigms. A paradigm is an
overall view of things in terms of which particular experiences can
be understood. Such a pattern helps us fit perceived facts into a
coherent picture and provides basic rules whereby we draw inferences
about our observations. If a few facts appear inconsistent with a
paradigm they are merely regarded as anomalies, not as reasons for
abandoning the paradigm. But too many awkward facts exert pressure to
find a way of looking at things that handles observations more
gracefully. A scientific revolution, or paradigm shift, may then
occur. [Footnote
17] Ptolemy's
earth-centered astronomy was a paradigm until the Copernican
revolution replaced it. The Aristotelian paradigm in physics was
displaced by the Newtonian system, itself overthrown by relativity
theory in the twentieth century. Footnote
18
Paradigms
are not just found in the physical sciences. Political observers must
process their experiences; if they do not employ a conscious
paradigm, they will use an unconscious one.
It
may not matter whether people whose political actions we observe
(votes, speeches, donations, expenditures, aggressions) understand
their own paradigms. But as observers, it is important for us to be
self-conscious about ours. Paradigms always incorporate assumptions.
These may be incompatible with each other or with experience. It is
impossible, however, to reject an assumption that we do not know we
have made.
Some
people claim we should abandon all "metaphysical"
speculations, never assuming anything. Their advice cannot be
followed. The only alternatives to conscious assumptions are
unconscious ones. Mere awareness that we are assuming something is
therefore no basis for rejecting a belief The physical sciences
themselves rest upon assumptions not provable by scientific methods.
Awareness of our assumptions can clarify our thought, help us to
become more consistent, and enable us to abandon those ideas whose
implications we are not prepared to accept.
Consistency.
This brings us to a third strategy for thinking about politics: we
should strive for consistent analysis. There are naturally many
different ways to interpret any particular fact or limited area of
experience. Each interpretation may be compatible with evidence about
these limited areas. Nonvoting, for example, may be a sign of extreme
alienation, hostility to the very foundations of a political system.
But it might only mean that these people are not interested in
politics.
When
a senator votes against a bill, what does it mean? Does it mean he
opposes the bill's stated objective ("helping the poor,"
for example) or does he doubt the bill will produce the intended
results? Does he think the bill uses the wrong means to promoting its
objectives, or is he voting against his own views because the bill is
unpopular back home and he wants to be re-elected? Is he swapping his
vote on this bill, which he somewhat favors, to get another senator's
support on a more crucial bill? If we are considering a senator's
single action, many conflicting interpretations can be put upon it.
It
is harder to find a satisfying, consistent interpretation of a larger
range of facts. The fewer facts we know, the more assumptions we must
make in interpreting any one of them; the more assumptions, the more
flexible our analysis and the easier to defend each of the
conflicting interpretations. As we learn more facts, however, they
become harder to account for. Explanations based on assumptions that
conflict with other facts must now be ruled out, which leaves us with
fewer possible explanations. For example, if the senator voting
against the bill also strongly supported other bills aimed at the
same objective, this tends to contradict explanations of his present
actions based on the assumption he is hostile to the bill's goal.
Consistency
in applying assumptions forces us to think about more than one thing
at a time. We cannot just assume one thing for one purpose and the
opposite thing for other purposes. Assumptions made for one purpose
must be applied across the board, wherever they have implications.
Any experience that appears to contradict any generalization is
relevant.
If
we want to assume that Earl Warren was a dedicated Communist in order
to explain his behavior as Chief Justice, [Footnote
19] we
must also assume that he was either a Communist while governor of
California or became one after going on to the Supreme Court. If we
find that Warren's record as governor is not that of a Communist, we
must conclude that he was converted or that he never was a Communist
at all. If we also want to assume that President Eisenhower was a
Communist, as the John Birch Society founder charged, we then face a
possible dilemma: If Ike was a Communist, why would he appoint a
non-Communist as Chief Justice? The question can be answered, but
this might require additional assumptions, some of which could
conflict with other available facts.
Of
course in political life principled, consistent analysis is not
always prominent. A politician who can get what he wants by accusing
opponents of mutually incompatible sins will not always opt for
consistency. Nor will loudly proclaimed principles necessarily
prevail when leaders decide they can get better results by violating
them. President Thomas Jefferson, a strict constructionist who argued
that government could do nothing not expressly authorized by the
Constitution, disregarded this principle to buy the Louisiana ter
ritory when the opportunity arose in 1 803. The principle, at best a
dubious one, was perhaps best ignored; the Louisiana Purchase
provided vast new horizons for American expansion. President Nixon
imposed wage and price controls in 1971 after denouncing such
controls for 20 years. Nixon's principle was probably sound and the
action economically unwise, but he correctly saw that controls would
be good politics.
Southern
senators claiming principles that barred voting cloture to end a
filibuster against civil rights legislation, supported shutdown of a
liberal filibuster against renewing the draft during the Vietnam War.
When Justice John Marshall Harlan (the elder)Footnote
20 issued
his famous dissenting opinion that "our Constitution is
colorblind" in the Plessy v. Ferguson case (1896), he became the
hero of civil rights advocates. The Court's Plessy decision upholding
laws requiring "separate but equal" facilities for black
people was not swept away until the desegregation cases of the 1950s.
By the late 1960s a law school casebook edited by civil rights
enthusiasts deleted Harlan's "colorblind" remark-probably
the most quoted line from any dissenting opinion in our judicial
history. The previously favored principle of colorblindness was now
an awkwardness for people urging racial balancing, busing, quotas,
and other activities in which an individual's race cannot be ignored.
That
political actions do not always show great concern for principled
consistency may be disheartening. But this does not justify our being
unprincipled in our thinking about politics. There is, presumably,
some distinction between politics and political science, just as
there is between crime and criminology.
THE PRESENT
CONSTITUTIONAL PARADIGM
Americans
tend to think about politics in terms of categories suggested by the
Constitution. Our Constitution is thus not just a set of legal rules;
it is also a paradigm. It is the basis of our thinking about
government as well as the basis of our government. For example, from
our youngest years we are taught to see a government composed of
three branches: legislative, executive, and judicial. Wielding
separated powers, these branches are said to constitute checks and
balances upon each other, preventing any one part of government from
running amuck.
Another
major element of our constitutional paradigm is federalism, dividing
powers and responsibilities between the central government and those
of the various states. Our paradigm also places heavy emphasis on
individual "rights," especially the right not to be
deprived of "life, liberty, or property" without "due
process of law." We will think about all of these things in due
course. Our constitutional paradigm still has enough validity that no
text on American government can omit chapters on the three branches.
Here, these mandatory discussions will be found in Chapters 5, 7, and
8.
No
doubt the present constitutional paradigm is vastly better than
nothing. It provides a basic map of many governmental institutions,
indicating important connections between them. It provides us with a
reasonably sophisticated political vocabulary. Any person who
understands key constitutional terms has a good foundation for
thinking about politics. The Constitution is full of important terms
and concepts, such as impeachment, treason, treaty, pardons, full
faith and credit, freedom of speech, unreasonable searches, trial by
jury, habeas corpus, ex post facto, and equal protection of the laws.
Inadequacies
of the Present Constitutional Paradigm
New
Elements in American Life. Many of today's institutions, never
anticipated by the founding fathers, are not mentioned at all in the
Constitution. The federal bureaucracy is a prime example. Only a few
hundred people were employed by the early federal government. Even by
1871, only 53,000 civilians were on the payroll. [Footnote
21] Nobody
at the 1787 convention could have foreseen the nearly three million
federal civil servants by the 1980s. After all, our total population
in 1789 was only about four million.
Civil
Service. The Constitution naturally has little to say about the civil
service. It does provide that the president "may require the
opinion, in writing, of the principal officer in each of the
executive departments, upon any subject relating to the duties of
their respective offices" (Article II, Section 2.) And the same
article decrees that the president shall "nominate, and by and
with the advice and consent of the Senate, shall appoint ambassadors,
other public ministers and consuls, judges of the Supreme Court, and
all other officers of the United States, whose appointments are not
herein otherwise provided for, and which shall be established by
law." This last power is qualified, however, by a provision that
"The Congress may by law vest the appointment of such inferior
officers, as they think proper, in the president alone, in the courts
of law, or in the heads of departments." Aside from a provision
in Article IV that "all executive officers" (among others)
"shall be bound by oath or affirmation to support this
constitution," the Constitution says nothing else applying
specifically to bureaucracy.
Corporations.
The Constitution is also silent about big corporations. Some
corporations did exist by 1787, but they were relatively small. Large
corporations only emerged with nineteenth-century industrialization.
The super-corporations now dominating our economic landscape--General
Motors, General Electric, General Dynamics, Boeing, RCA, CBS--are
recent developments. In 1787 typical Americans lived and worked on
family farms or in small towns. Today, they work for huge
corporations or for large ones, all gigantic by 1787 standards. Yet
the Constitution does not even provide for federal chartering of
corporations. Nearly all American corporations are chartered under
state laws.
Commenting
on this state of affairs, a prominent legal scholar has pointed out
that:
The
corporation . . . is a constitutional anomaly, a creature that cannot
be understood in terms of three-hundred- year-old political theory
from John Locke or even in terms of later theory from Thomas
Jefferson. The classical economic theory of Adam Smith . . . is also
inadequate. The same may be said for the underlying theory of the
American Constitution, which assumes that only two entities--the
individual natural person and government-- exist or are important. By
making no provision for collective activity (the corporation, the
trade union, the political party, among others) classical political
theory is now outmoded. Footnote
22
Political
Parties. As this passage notes, the Constitutionignores unions and
political parties as well as corporations. The founding fathersknew
about parties, which were already well-established in England, but
they werelargely hostile to parties, regarding them as obstacles to
good government. While The Federalist complains eloquently about the
"mischiefs of faction," the Constitution itself simply
ignores the subject. Of course, parties did not take the hint and
vanish and have, indeed, strongly influenced American government.
Perhaps most dramatically, party discipline has prevented the
Electoral College from functioning as intended. Instead of
deliberating independently, it simply reflects the majority vote for
president in the respective states. Thus, no one can understand how
the president is actually chosen merely by reading the Constitution.
Labor
Unions. As for labor unions, neither the Constitution nor The
Federalist mentions them at all. The founders would undoubtedly be
just as amazed by the AFL-CIO, the UAW, and the Teamsters as by the
giant corporations. Some of them might be horrified to learn that
their concept of "checks and balances" may have encouraged
enactment of pro-union laws as a way of controlling corporations. The
founders might be amused to find that these unions, governmentally
encouraged to limit concentrations of private power, later turned to
"organizing" government employees.
Education
and Ecology. Many other important things are not dealt with by the
Constitution. Mass higher education was constitutionally unheralded.
Not even Benjamin Franklin foresaw inventions like radio and TV or
their impact on American politics. The founders would have been
astounded to learn that President Kennedy would promise the moon and
President Nixon would deliver it. Early America had low population
densities, apparently limitless natural resources, and production
based chiefly on human and animal labor. How could the founders have
anticipated environmental pollution or energy problems?
Cities.
Consider urbanization! In 1787 America had few cities, none of them
big. Constitutional silence makes cities, except for Washington,
D.C., entirely creatures of state government. They can be formed,
dissolved, consolidated, etc., by simple action of their state
legislature. The relation between states and cities is not analogous
to that of federal government and states. It is not a federal
relationship, but a strictly hierarchical, inferior-superior one. And
the cities, according to a literal interpretation of the
Constitution, have no direct dealings with the federal government.
Of
course, this description of cities is now almost completely untrue.
Vast federal grants go directly to city governments for specific
purposes or through general "revenue-sharing" programs.
Attached to these grants are many strings, federal requirements whose
violation leads to a cut-off of future money. Congress has also begun
enacting legislation directly restricting how cities as well as state
governments can be organized. For example, many cities cannot
redistrict councilman elections, or change from single-member
districts to at-large elections, without prior consent from
Washington. Footnote
23
Exceptions
to the Constitutional Rule. As the problem of cities indicates,
fitting actualities into the pattern suggested by the Constitution
becomes ever more difficult. Even institutions actually provided for
in the document do not function as it suggests.
In
the Legislature. Congress, for example, is not the national
legislature. It does enact some laws, but its members appear to
devote most of their time, energy, and staff to other things. Members
of Congress act as "ombudsmen," troubleshooters for baffled
constituents unable to get satisfaction or sometimes even attention
from various bureaucratic agencies. They campaign for re-election.
They negotiate details of government spending: how much will be spent
on highways, dams, military tanks, and where it will be spent. They
hold hearings. They investigate. They go on trips (or "junkets,"
as they are called by critics).
While
Congress, supposedly the legislature, spends most of its time
otherwise, other agencies are busy legislating. The courts formulate
legal rules as they decide their cases. The president issues
executive orders having the force of law. Each month, bureaucratic
agencies issue thousands of pages of new legal rules, all published
in the voluminous Federal Register.
According
to the constitutional paradigm, legislation is what the legislature
does. People have therefore been reluctant to call the work of other
agencies "legislation." To handle this problem, the
expression "quasi-legislative" was invented when the
bureaucracy was in its period of rapid growth. Likewise,
"quasi-judicial" was devised to refer to adjudication by
the independent regulatory agencies, which conflicted with the
constitutional paradigm's implication that adjudication (employment
of general rules to decide specific cases) was a function of the
courts.
In
the Judiciary. To say that courts are the judiciary no longer
adequately describes American government. Likewise, courts are now
doing things our constitutional paradigm would have us expect the
executive or legislative branches to handle. Outstanding examples are
those court decisions ordering money spent even though no legislature
has appropriated it. [Footnote
24] When
a federal court orders a state or local government to spend money,
expectations deriving from the "federalism" component of
our paradigm are confounded. Such orders directed against another
branch of the federal government raise the issue of separation of
powers, as well as offend the specific constitutional provision that
"no money shall be drawn from the treasury, but in consequences
of appropriations made by law" (Article 1, Section 9).
Expansion
of the Constitutional Regulations: The Amendments. The paradigm
suggested by our Constitution is inadequate also because judicial
interpretations have gone far beyond its literal words. Nearly 200
years of interpretations have accumulated. The Supreme Court alone
has written more than 400 volumes of decisions, and in the process
the interpretations seem to have swallowed up the document. In many
respects our actual Constitution is therefore just as "unwritten"
as that of Great Britain. Today, to study American constitutional
law, you do not read the Constitution; you read leading Supreme Court
decisions.
On
Church and State. For example, the Bill of Rights, taken literally,
restricts only the central government. The First Amendment, setting
the tone for the whole, begins "Congress shall make no law
respecting an establishment of religion . . ." (emphasis added).
The Bill of Rights was added to appease people who were skeptical of
the new document, but whose support was needed to secure
ratification. These skeptics feared that a stronger central
government might abuse its powers. They were not worried about abuses
by state governments, whose powers were certainly not increased by
the new Constitution. Accordingly, the Bill of Rights restricted only
the federal government.
When
the Bill of Rights was ratified, some state governments still had
established churches. No one thought that the First Amendment, with
its prohibition against the establishment of a church by Congress,
made it unconstitutional for a state legislature to do so. Since the
1930s, however, the Supreme Court has gradually expanded the meaning
attributed to the Bill of Rights; today, most of its provisions are
considered restrictions on state governments. Thus, by 1948, the
Supreme Court had struck down an Illinois public school "released
time for religious education" program as a violation of the
Establishment Clause of the First Amendment. Footnote
25
On
Capital Punishment. The capital punishment cases are other examples
of judicial conclusions extracted from the literal Constitution only
with considerable imagination. In 1972 the Supreme Court struck down
all existing death penalty provisions, in spite of explicit
constitutional provisions for capital punishment: In the Fifth
Amendment, the Grand Jury Clause refers to a "capital crime";
the Double Jeopardy Clause, to being "twice put in jeopardy of
life or limb," and the Due Process Clause, to the right not to
be "deprived of life, liberty, or property, without due process
of law" (emphasis added). Likewise, deprivations of life with
due process of law are expressly contemplated by the Fourteenth
Amendment. The Supreme Court justices, however, apparently based
their decision in Furman V. Georgia [Footnote
26] on
the haphazard and discriminatory way death sentences were imposed.
Disproportionate numbers of those executed were poor or black,
implying denial of the equal protection of the laws. When several
states responded to this case by enacting mandatory death for certain
crimes, however, the Court struck this down, too. Such laws, denying
courts adequate chance to consider mitigating circumstances, were
"cruel and unusual" and violated the Eighth
Amendment. [Footnote
27] Still,
some new capital punishment statutes were upheld. Footnote
28
Two
justices, William Brennan and Thurgood Marshall, consistently voted
against capital punishment in every case. They argued that death is
inherently a "cruel and unusual" punishment, hence always a
violation of the Eighth Amendment. Here, certainly, was doctrine that
would have startled the founders, or anybody reading constitutional
language in a straightforward way. The Eighth Amendment with its
"cruel and unusual punishment" clause was enacted
simultaneously with the Fifth, which contains several overt
references to the death penalty. Why would the founders place
restrictions on circumstances in which death could be imposed in one
clause if they were banning it completely in another?
On
Corporate Law. A third important example of our judicially-
elaborated Constitution involves corporations. Corporations,
important centers of economic production, inevitably litigate a lot.
Courts have therefore had to decide to what extent constitutional
rights are enjoyed by corporations as well as individuals. The basic
legal question was whether a corporation is a "person" in
the sense that the term is used in the Constitution. For example, is
a corporation a "person" for purposes of the following
Fifth Amendment provisions (emphasis added)?
Nor
shall any person . . . be compelled in any criminal case to be a
witness against himself, nor be deprived of life, liberty, or
property, without due process of law. . . .
For
purposes of the Due Process and Equal Protection clauses, the courts
do consider a corporation to be a person and, hence, protected.
However for purposes of the Self-Incrimination Clause, as well as
Privileges and Immunities clauses in Article IV and the Fourteenth
Amendment, a corporation is not a person and, hence, is
unprotected. Footnote
29
New
World Experiences. A more basic cause of the inadequacy of our
political paradigm is that the Constitution is not based on the
principled analysis of human associations now possible. This is no
reflection on the founders. These men were unusually well educated.
They were avid readers, philosophically sophisticated and
historically well versed. Their document has lasted longer than any
other written constitution. But there has been a great deal of new
experience with governments during the last 200 years. The world has
changed from domination by monarchies to domination by republics. The
twentieth century alone witnessed the fall of monarchies in Russia,
Germany, Austria-Hungary, Turkey, China, and elsewhere. New patterns
of government have emerged and, sometimes, disappeared again. We have
the Nazis in Germany, the Fascists in Italy, the Peronists in
Argentina, and the Communists in the U.S.S.R. and elsewhere.
Governments peculiar to local conditions have developed in such
countries as Japan, Mexico, India, and Thailand. Since the end of
World War II in 1945, several large European colonial empires have
disintegrated. Three world wars have already been fought in the
twentieth century: World War I in Europe (1914-1918), World War II in
Europe, the Far East, and the South Pacific (1939-1945), and World
War III (1964-1975), the overt hostilities of which were largely
conducted in Vietnam, Laos, and Cambodia.
Surely
what has happened abroad since 1787 can teach us something about
human associations; but much can also be gained by studying internal
developments. Every foreign war has had domestic complications. The
Civil War proved to be educational as well as bloody. We have tried
many policies and programs-- the protective tariff, subsidies of
waterways, the Homestead Act, the Land Grant Colleges Act, antitrust
policy, conservation efforts--all leading, for example, to our
national parks, labor policy, housing policy, welfare policy, race
relations. Some of these experiments have been successful, others
have been disasters. All provide food for thought. In addition, the
United States has many governments. There are the fifty states and
almost 80,000 lower units of government: cities, counties, education
districts, mosquito control districts, library districts, irrigation
districts, and so forth. Our country has been called a "laboratory
of federalism" because each government is a center of
experiments from which new knowledge may be distilled.
Should We
Go Beyond the Present Constitution?
Increasing
numbers of talented lawyers and academicians are trying to think
methodically about the experience we are accumulating. This, too, is
an asset which the founding fathers did not have. We have more
shoulders to stand on than the founders did, including theirs; it is
no reflection on them that we may be able to see a little further
along the road. Therefore, we can say that not only is it possible to
go beyond the paradigm of the present Constitution, but it is
advisable. Under present conditions, misunderstandings which would
have been harmless in former times have become harmful indeed. For
example, we will see that the term "law" was used in the
Constitution in at least three very different senses. Confusions in
these three meanings were inconsequential as long as government
bureaucracy was small, budgets were tiny, and there was little
regulation of the national economy. We will see, however, that under
present conditions a paradigm blurring or concealing the distinction
between these three different meanings of "law" is highly
mischievous. This is especially true when the body failing to make
the distinction is the Supreme Court of the United States.
SUMMARY
As
we have seen, complex societies and events can easily seem like
unfathomable chaos. Complexity forces us to rely on language-symbols
referring to categories of experience-in order to gather and process
the countless individual observations necessary to put together an
inferential picture of invisible government. Language, with its
classification of merely similar things into identical categories, is
part of a more general strategy of simplification which we can use in
grappling with complexity. Another strategy is to think in terms of a
"paradigm," an overall view of things in terms of which
particular experiences can be understood. Still another strategy is
to test ideas for consistency both with our other ideas and with
experience.
The
American Constitution is, among other things, a paradigm. It provides
us with an overall view of our government, enabling us to put details
into perspective and to see how they fit into the larger picture. It
gives us the basic categories in terms of which we perceive and think
about government. Unfortunately, our Constitution is now inadequate.
Among the important elements that it does not put into place are some
of the most important parts of today's political experience:
bureaucracy, giant corporations, political parties, unions, mass
higher education, and urbanization. When a paradigm conflicts this
baldly with experience, it no longer serves its purpose. But it is an
old political axiom that you cannot replace something with nothing.
In the following chapters, we will be thinking together about
politics from the perspectives suggested by a possible replacement
for the present Constitutional paradigm.
QUESTIONS
FOR DISCUSSION
1.
Define an inference and give an example of one.
2.
Who is the president of the United States at this moment? To what
extent is your answer an inference?
3.
Why can we not rely on personal observation for all of our knowledge
about American politics?
4.
As this chapter notes, many murder victims are criminals killed by
other criminals trying to get or keep a piece of the action. If we
assume that these victims are no loss to society, does it not follow
that their murderers are performing a public service? How could we
arrive at a contrary conclusion without rejecting the assumption?
5.
It is easy enough to see why we should seek simplicity. But why
should we also "distrust it"?
6.
Pick an example from recent political events that can be interpreted
more than one way, and explain briefly some of the different
interpretations which can be placed upon it.
7.
If that government is indeed best which governs least, why not
anarchy?
8.
What is the purpose for raising, in this text, the issue of Earl
Warren's alleged membership in the Communist Party? Is your answer
to this question an inference? Explain why or why not.
9.
What are some differences between politics and political science?
10.
What does it mean to say that the Constitution is a paradigm as well
as a body of legal rules?
11.
Considering that our Constitution does not mention political
parties, corporations, and labor unions, how can it provide the
basis for a government that works as well as ours does under modern
conditions?
12.
List a number of ways in which the world has changed since the year
the Constitution was written. Also list some ways it has remained
the same. Which list is more important? What are your criteria for
determining importance? Do you think on the whole, since 1789,
things have changed for the better, or for the worse? Why? How do
you suppose future students, looking back on our time from the
perspective of 200 years, will answer similar questions?
13.
How do you react to the unorthodox assertion that the Vietnam
involvement can be considered the third world war? Just because it
is not presently fashionable to do so, is it wrong to classify it as
such? What qualities must a war have to constitute a world war? Who
has the right to decide?
*************
To access
other chapters,
go back to the Table of Contents.
Footnotes
*
Harold B. Acton, The Morals of Markets (London: Longman Group Ltd.,
1971), p. 92.
1.
Gilbert and Sullivan, Patience (1881).
2.
Quoted in Forbes, November 15, 1975, p. 13.
3.
See John Godfrey Saxe, "The Blind Men and the Elephant," in
George Hornby (ed.), Poemsfor Children and Other People, New York:
Crown Publishers, 1975, p. 52.
4.
Walter Gellhom, "The Abuse of Occupational Licensing," 44
University of Chicago Law Review 6 (1976), p. 14.
5.
New York Times, February 22, 1977.
6.
New York Times, August 7, 1969.
7.
Oregon Statesman, July 22, 1977.
8.
Boston Globe, January 10, 1971.
9.
Christian Science Monitor, August 15, 1977.
10.
Toledo Blade, September 14, 1975.
11.
H. F. Pringle, The Life and Times of William Howard Taft. New York:
Farrar and Rinehart, 1939, Vol. 1, p. 381.
12.
Adrian Daily Telegram, November 1, 1977.
13.
Time, date uncertain.
14.
Toledo Blade, May 15, 1977.
15.
Toledo Blade, December 10, 1972.
16.
Aristotle, Ethics. Baltimore: Penguin, 1953, pp. 65-66.
17.
Thomas S. Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 1962.
18.
The current orthodoxy in physics has not gone unchallenged. See
especially the works of Dewey B. Larson, whose work helped inspire
the present text in many ways: The Structure of the Physical Universe
(1959), The Case against the Nuclear Atom (1963), Beyond Newton
(1964), New Light on Space and Time (1965), Quasars and Pulsars
(1971), Nothing but Motion (1979). Portland, Oregon: North Pacific
Publishers.
19.
See John A. Stormer, None Dare Call It Treason. Florissant, Missouri.
Liberty Bell Press, 1964.
20.
John Marshall Harlan, who served on the Supreme Court from 1877 to
191 1. Not to be confused with his grandson with the same name, who
served on the Supreme Court from 1955 to 1970.
21.
Leonard D. White, The Republican Era. New York: Free Press, 1958, p.
2.
22.
Arthur Selwyn Miller, The Supreme Court and American Capitalism. New
York: Free Press, 1968, pp. 7-8.
23.
See City of Richmond v. U.S., 422 U.S. 358 (1975).
24.
Millikan v. Bradley (11) 433 U.S. 267 (1977).
25.
McCollum v. Board of Education, 333 U.S. 203 (1948).
26.
Furman v. Georgia, 408 U.S. 238 (1972).
27.
Gregg v. Georgia, 428 U.S. 153 (1976).
28.
Roberts v. Louisiana, 428 U.S. 325 (1977).
29.
Santa Clara County v. S. Pac. RR Co., 118 U.S. 394 (1886); Ozborn v.
Ozlin, 310 U.S. 53 (1940); B & 0 RR Co. v. L CC, 221 U.S. 612
(191 1).